Hi everyone, I'm excited to announce that the eight week online Transcend Course is back. Become certified in learning the latest science of human potential and learn how to live
a more fulfilling, meaningful, creative, and self actualized life. The new cohort starts on June twenty fifth and will include more than ten hours of recorded lectures, live group Q and A sessions with me, small group sessions with our world class faculty, a plethora of resources and articles to support your learning, and an exclusive workbook of growth challenges that will help you overcome your deepest fears and grow as a whole person. There are even some personalized self
actualization coaching spots available with our world class faculty. As an add on, I'm happy to announce that just for Psychology podcast listeners, you can get twenty percent off the course but going to transcendcourse dot com and entering psych Podcast in the coupon box. We will be closing registration soon, so I suggest signing up as soon as possible. We have so much fun in this course and you will receive a lot of support along your self actualization journey.
Just go to transcendcourse dot com to register and enter psych podcast psych Podcast In the coupon box, I look forward to welcoming you to the transcender community.
There ain't nobody else making our choices but us. We might like to think so, but we're responsible and that's scary, but it's also tremendously empowering if you fully grasp it.
Hello, and welcome to the Psychology Podcast. Today we welcome back Ken Sheldon to the show. Ken is a Curator's Distinguished Professor of psychological Science at the University of Columbia, Missouri. He has written and edited over two hundred academic books, scholarly articles, and book chapters. Among these, some of his most notable work include Optimal Human Being and self determination Theory in the Clinic. His latest book is called Freely Determined.
What the New Psychology of the Self teach us about how to live. In this episode, I talked to Ken Sheldon about free will. Instead of questioning its existence, Ken is concerned with how we might use free will to help us reach our goals. Each person has the capacity to make good and bad choices and to learn from the past. Although we are unable to know everything about ourselves, we can still make informed decisions. Believing that we have
the ability to choose directly affects our well being. In values, we also touch on the topics of neuroscience, self determination, and responsibility. I really enjoy this conversation with Ken. I find him really insightful, and especially when it comes to this quite heated topic within academia, this topic of do we have free will or not? I like his perspective. I think it's fresh, and I think it really draws a lot on psychological science as opposed to maybe more
metaphysical ideas. Wherever you stand in the free will debate, we'd love to hear from you. Please come into the comments, and at the very least, I hope this conversation stimulated some deep thought and reflection on this very important and fascinating topic. So, without further ado, I bring you Ken Sheldon again. It's so great to have you on the Psychology Podcast.
Yeah, it's great to be here. I think I was with you a few years ago, but things have kind of changed a little bit since then, so it'll be good to reconnect. Yeah.
Absolutely, a lot has changed in the world. And the last time we talked about your brilliant work on the optimal Human. So you wrote this fastening new book called Freely Determined. I had to take the cover off because it's hard to read it with the cover fallen off. But anyway, Freely Determined, congratulations on the publication of this book, and it adds some new ideas into this space, this
free will debate space. I noticed you don't get too mirrored down in the philosophy of mind rigorous nuanced debate, you know, and you know you don't even stake a position. I don't think you anywhere in the book did you say I'm a compatibilist. You know. I feel like you focus a lot on the psychology of it, But what are you within that whole debate? Like, are you a compatibilist? Are you something else?
Probably you would call me a compatibilist. What I'm trying to say is that you can have determinism and free will at the same time. You just have to recognize that human higher mental processes are part of the determining formula. You know that what we do weigh up here in this abstract mental world that we live in, is part of what determines the behaviors that we take. And I don't think that it's reducible to any of the lower level machinery. The machinery gives us the capacity to do
what we do, but it doesn't determine what we do. Instead, we selves attempting to operate our own minds, taking advantage of all this machinery. We have really kind of running the show for better or worse.
This sounds like a debate that you have with your father. Is that right, He's a very deterministic view of the situation.
Yeah. I start off the book talking about these debates going you know, way back into my teens with my dad, who was a law professor and but also a determinist was kind of a funny thing. He didn't think people should be punished for their crimes because they couldn't help doing them. But I, you know, I had the hardest time because his arguments were so undefeatable in some ways.
And so you could say that my whole career as a personality psychologist has been about trying to find ways around those arguments or ways to think about them differently. That gives us, you know, a viable position as mental entities for taking control of our own lives and for leading the kind of lives that we think we would like. That's just it.
The leading the lives that we think well, the leading the lives that we hopefully would like, because you go through a lot sorting out the difference, how to find out the difference between what we think we might like and what we do like. So I'm going to give you a little bit more credit than you just gave yourself there. I'm about you know the kind of life right, you know, because you go great pains just to for us to really look deep inside and figure that out.
You know, like, there are a lot of things that we think we should like. There's even things we might think we like and we don't really like.
Yeah, yeah, it's not easy. No, we're in this funny position. Having free will means we are also free to make mistakes. We're free to be clueless, We're free to have no idea what we really want. We're free to make terrible choices, but we're also free to learn from those choices and
hopefully make better ones in the future. So, you know, the book kind of talks about the free will debate early on, and it doesn't really take a position, as you said, It just concludes that there's reasonable doubt pretty good reason for doubting the determinist's perspective. And then it moves on to what I think is a more important question of Okay, if we do have free will, as I'm claiming or saying this probable, how well are we
able to use it? And that I think is the really important question, because we're kind of cut off, you know, we're living in this mental world system. To Daniel Cottaman called it the tyranny of the prefrontal cortex. We're sort
of suspended above the machinery above. We have the ability to be out of touch with ourselves, and so critical question is to get the information, the good information that we need to make choices that are going to cause our entire organism to thrive, even though we're kind of stuck as the conscious representatives of that organism moment to moment, and we might be pretty clueless about what's really happening inside of us.
It just seems like you somehow make a distinction between system one being, you know, our unconscious mind so to speak, that all the things beneath the surface of our conscious awareness that are happening automatically kind of keeping the system running without much pre thought. It seems like that system one you try be a lot less free will to than system two, which you talk a lot about the
symbolic mind, which we'll get to in a second. Yeah, and system two being our ability to plan, to error, correct, to change course, to maybe influence our system one. You know that we can influence our system one by changing habits, can't we? You know, it's not like a system one is completely impenetrable.
That's right, that's right.
So you actually like weigh the two systems differently in terms of their free will implications.
I asked a very excellent question. I haven't thought about it quite that way, but I would agree with that assessment in the book I adapt A philosopher, Christian Lists. He wrote a book in twenty nineteen called Why free Will Is Real, and he proposed a definition of free will that put the question squarely into my territory as
a goal researcher. And he said, free will is nothing more than the ability to ask yourself what you want, call up from your non conscious mind some possibilities for action, choose one of them, and then get moving. And so that's really a pretty straightforward and kind of intuitive perspective. If you think about it. What does it mean for an agent to have free will? It can think about what it wants, and then it can decide, and then
it can start trying to get it. And so that's what I've been studying my whole career is how people set goals and how well do they pursue goals, and then how do the goals influence their happiness after they're done pursuing them and perhaps achieving them. So I really love that definition that a Christian List provided because it sort of helped me sidestep these centuries of philosophical debate, which I see as pretty impenetrable and very much bogged down.
Everybody's got their own position, and I love the ability to sidestep all that and say, well, simple free will is the ability to think about what you want to make a choice, and that is a system to process. It's there's a lot of conscious stuff going on there where we say, well, wait a minute, what do I do here? Well, I could do this, that or that? What do I want to do? We think about the future, what will happen in each case? I think, I like
option B, I'm going to go for that. And so that's not something that's happening in system one, or at least not in that same way, because System one is more sort of automatic and habitual. So the system too is the part of us that is kind of in a representational world, living in a symbolic self. We can talk about that, making choices between alternatives.
Yeah, I gotta say, I love your perspective because it's very much in the line with my perspective, and I have framed it a little bit differently. I've called it cybernetic free will, but I think we're talking about the same thing, you know, where cybernetic systems that can can consciously represent the distance between our starting state and our goal state, we can try to consciously develop strategies to reduce that gap so we can get to where we
want to go. I mean, I studied, I studied with Herbert Simon, so I came from that whole, that whole school of you know, goal stuff.
I love the cybernetic perspective because it underlies the car Shire approach, which is the main correct perspective that I use in my goal research.
Beautiful, Yeah, beautiful. And I don't know if you follow my colleague Colin Deyong's work at all on cybernetic Big five theory.
Yeah, yeah, I do know his word.
But cool, yeah, very interesting. So I believe in that perspective, and I would just call it cybernetic free will, as
distinguished from magic free will. But both of us agree, I mean, anyone with a with a with a sane mind agrees that that there are we're not outside the causal structure of nature, that even our system two processes are caused by a long series of chain of things that that obviously lay out way outside out of our understanding, comprehension knowledge, going very very far back, maybe even to the Big Bang.
Right, I would say that the system two processes are enabled by lots of stuff, and they're influenced by lots of stuff, a lot of it that we don't know about, but that the moment for choice comes, and that the conscious experience of that's the one I want, flips the brain into an implemental state. It crosses the rubicon, to
use Peter Golwitzer's terminology. And so I don't think that you can predict what the decision of that self of the moment is going to be, because it depends on what it wants, and it's a sort of not independent but somewhat independent process going on in the universe that, again is enabled by all the machinery. But I don't think it makes any sense to say me agreeing to come on your show was predetermined since the Big Bang, you know, or anything else that you or I did today.
It also doesn't make sense to say that we're magically outside of all that physical stuff. Again, we're influenced by it and enabled by it. But you know, I think we have a certain degree of independence from it, and that's the independence that allows us to make terrible mistakes. We can even commit suicide. No other animal does that, you know. I mean, that's the ultimate insult to personal survival. We can get so confused that we could take our own life, you know, And that might be Actually I
don't think it is. But the ultimate act of free will is just to deny your self existence. But more probably as are people who have a lot of emotional problems that are controlling their decision making to an unhealthy extent.
Well, I mean, couldn't someone argue that? Probabilistically speaking, Once you start adding up enough factors external, environmental and internal factors, suicide ideation starts to get more and more and more and more likely. You know, certainly there's there are still causes, you know that that allow us to do something. I mean, we were in the social sciences. We don't think we can't predict things at all, And I just think there are some things that have very high correlations, like so strong.
For instance, if you find someone I just thought this an example on the spot, but I was thinking, you find someone who's a devout vegetarian or a devout vegan for thirty years, you can predict if you go to a restaurant, you know they're not going to order that cheeseburger, like I guess. The question is if you can predict that with pretty much one hundred percent accuracy, are you saying that vegan person had no free will in that matter to choose the burger? I guess they could have.
I guess they could have, But they could have. We could predict they wouldn't unless they thought of unless they knew that we were trying to predict them, and then they wanted to consciously defy us, and then maybe that was their active free will.
I don't know, well, I don't know if it's fair to say that when we are able to know what we want and consistently do it, that we are determined to do that thing. It's more than you're able to detect and follow our own preferences. And so that person knows they're not going to eat meat. It's not like they have a compulsion not to eat meat, or maybe they sort of do it, maybe it's kind of gross to them, But I would put it that they have a very strongly internalized value of not eating meat, and
that to express that value in their choices. And you know, if suddenly they were starving and meat was all there was, I'm sure they could go against that value or overcome that determinism in favor of staying alive.
Wow. Yeah, Okay, this is a good point. You use the word compulsion. You know, a lot of philosophers are free will will argue from a compatibilist point of view that that we have freedom as long as we're not compulsively you know, like there's a number of conditions that have to be met, and one of them is, you know, not internal distractions that cause us to have compulsions or or being externally controlled, like being tied down right and being told you must eat meat right or something like
that. That was a weird example, very weird, very weird.
But anyway, actually, my grand my grandfather did my father in law did that to my daughter one time to Thanksgiving dinner. You must eat. She was a vegetarian, quite obnoxious, let me tell you. Wow.
Wow. I hope the young lady did not grow up with PDS PTSD from that.
Well. I would answer this this line of questioning by referring to self determination theory, which are underlies most of my work. And it makes a distinction between feeling a compulsion to do something, calls that introject did motivation, feel guilty you're making yourself do it, and internal motivation or internalized where you're fully standing behind behind it. And so if you are acting with a compulsion, it's true you do not feel as free. And that is, you know,
a long term finding of self determination theory. And when you act with that sense of not being free, it negatively affects your well being. So it's important to have a sense of acting freely. And I take a little bit of a stronger position in the book, and I say that it's always us making the choices, whether we feel compelled to compel to do them or not. We're
signing off on them. And you know, it's sort of that existential perspective where you know that Jean Paul Sart, where you're responsible no matter what you reveal who you are by your choices. Choices scary. You know, people might try to avoid from choice or or escape from freedom in Eric Frome's terms. Nevertheless, we're always responsible. And so I don't think we're off the hook by saying I
felt compelled to do that. I think the answer to that is, well, that's sort of an immature position to be doing your living your life from, and you should try to get over that, and with some work, maybe some therapy, hopefully you can.
Yeah, this tying it to self determination theory is fascinating. You know, you can hear the skeptics. I can hear their voice in my head saying, like, Okay, well, feeling like you have free will doesn't mean you have free will, like just feeling like you're autonomous. You know, it doesn't take away the fact that we don't. I mean, it's just a mirage, it's just an illusion. But then you know, you come back and you say, I mean, I think I could do like the whole artificial intelligence chat between
you and the other person. Even so, get your let me allow you to actually say it. I'm trying to predict what you would say right now. Is that any from a meta level of this discussion.
Just rephrase the question real quick for me. No.
I mean, I'm just seeing a conversation unfold between you and a skeptic, or not a skeptic, but a determinist, a hard determinist, or even a determinist who a soft even a soft determinist, you know within the field who's like, well, you know, just feeling like you're free doesn't make you free. It's you didn't have any control, You didn't have any choice over feeling free anyway.
Yeah. Yeah, Well that's a funny thing that self determination theory is not directly addressed the free will question. It is just said that the feeling of freedom is important. And so I am taking that additional step, and I'm even making the quite radical and it's I'm not fully
standing behind it, but I think it's plausible. The radical argument that free will is an evolved capacity of the human mind, again defining this capacity to ask ourselves what we want and make a choice and I think that, you know, given the complexity of you know, the social environments that we face, and you know, we have to be able to make it up on the fly and figure out what's going on and make decisions constantly. And so I think that's the capacity that we evolved, or
at least to ask ourselves, what do I want? Okay, I'll do this. That doesn't mean that there were no constraints on what we were doing, you know, of course, you know I I was hungry that I might choose to eat instead of you know, going to the library and checking out the book. But this point you raised about, but we don't know why we won't want something. We don't know why we made that choice, and so we
can't be free. I do take exception to that, because it makes it so the only free being is an omniscient entity that knows everything about itself, and of course we are not that. I don't think anything is that. If you insist that that's what free will means, then I have to agree with you. It does and exist because we don't know everything about ourselves, but we know enough, hopefully to keep sailing the ship, you know, through the seas of our lives, hopefully in some coherent direction towards
meaningful goals that we that we've chosen. Do we know why we've chosen those goals? No, we don't know the brain processes that you know, the neurons that summed and created that are making that choice. But on the other hand, we do know why we made that choice. That's the one we thought we wanted, and only we and our conscious experience at that moment were in a position to make that determination. So it's sort of tricky, you know.
It's that this is the kind of compatibilism that I'm talking about.
Well, did you did you any chance to watch my two part series with Sam Harris on free Will?
I did not get a chance to, but it's on my list for the Christmas break.
Amazing because we we kind of get at it a little bit. We go go at it a little bit. You know, he's a friend, but you know we have different opinions on this matter, and I can well imagine, Yeah, there was this sticking point where you know, he was talking about cello and how I love cell and how I'd love to teach him how to play cell and he said, I have no choice in the matter, I do not want to play cello. He's like, I do not have any motivation to play cello, so therefore I
have no free will in playing cello. And I said, that's ridiculous. Like we can do things we're not motivated to want to do, right, we can. That's the will, you know. That's like, you know, we can. You know, just because our system one is telling us we're not interested in something doesn't mean we can't use system two to push through something. It's not like I want to
motivate to go to the gym every time. But he just didn't see it that way, you know, and it was a little frustrating, probably for both of us in that conversation.
I can imagine the way I could see Sam coming to want to play the cello is if he's got this self concept of I'm not a musical guy. Yet at some level of him there's a talent circies that have been undeveloped, And after his conversation with you, perhaps he would have started to think a little bit about, well, you know what, that's not such a bad idea. I've always kind of half thought it might be fun to wear in a musical instrument. And you know, the cello
is really pretty nice. To start listening to cello pieces, and you could come around to wanting to play the cello, and it wouldn't be that he was overcoming his system one resistance. It would be that he was overcoming his inaccurate self concept. So that's one way to sort of flip it around.
Yeah, that's a very interesting reframing. You know, there's a quote that I love from William James where he said, my first act of free will shall be to believe in free will. I'm sure you're familiar.
With that quote, right, Yeah, yeah, I've heard it.
I'm sure you have. I'm sure you have. The context surrounding that quote is really even more interesting because he suffered with depression and even some suicidal thoughts in his life, deep deep depression. And apparently after he said that and made that deliberation, his whole life changed. And it's fascinating to think the extent to which those beliefs matter within our own head. I mean, Sam, by the way, Sam Harris would be the first one to argue that belief matters.
I mean, that's why he rails against religions, fundamentalist religions that maybe have some dangerous ideologies. You know, obviously the contents of our mind can influence greatly how we act in the world, in our agency. So it just seems like you're arguing in a lot of ways that the stories that we tell ourselves with the symbolical mind, that that matters for our free will. It sounds like that's a big part of what you're saying. Is that right?
It is because in order to make choices between the alternatives that we have called into our minds, there has to be a sense of being a person who cares. And I call this the symbolic self. I draw from some work by Constantine set Katy's and John Scarnsky, on the evolution of the symbolic Self, a fascinating nineteen ninety seven article, and they said that in order for us to interact in this complex social world with language, all these other humans, we needed to evolve a sense of
being a person with a history and preferences. And we feel ourselves being that person, even though in a census just a hallucination. You know, it's a product of our minds. But I'm making the argument that it has top down control or some degree or influence at least over the choices that get made according to its own preferences. So it comes down to this sort of hierarchical perspective on the organization of matter that I talk about in one of the chapters.
In reclok And I don't know if you want to get into that, but I'll just say briefly that I think that evolution and has in the process of life evolving, more and more complex levels of control have showed up, and each one is been selected for because it regulates
the level below. Right, So when the first cell had to have the capacity to regulate the chemicals coming in and out of the cell, the first multicellular organism had to have a capacity to regulate how the different cells we're interacting with each other.
Eventually we've got a nervous system that takes control of that. And so I follow that logic all the way up, and I say, well, you've got a brain, and then you've got cognitive processes controlling that brain, and then you've got self processes controlling the cognitive processes. So that's where our own sort of agency originates. But then it continues up from there. We are nested within social relationships and
social spheres and those can try to control us. And that's a lot of what self determination theory is about, is how we deal with feeling controlled by other people. And it says people with power over us should support our autonomy so that we can maximize our sense of self determination and get the benefits of being embedded in these social relationships instead of just being oppressed by them.
So it's a really unique, I think, way of framing kind of an old idea that goes back to the tompt French theorist in the nineteenth century, the hierarchy of the sciences, And this is something I believe pretty strongly that each new level of organization builds upon the rest, but it is somewhat independent of what's below, given its ability to regulate what happens down below. So if I decide to go off for a run this morning, I
don't usually do that, but I suppose I did. Suddenly my all physical stuff in my body is having to deal with the stress of running, the physiology, and that was all determined by a conscious decision I made that morning. And so the hard headed skeptic is going to say, well, you don't know why you chose to run and I could say, well, I don't know where that idea came from, but I liked it and I picked it. That's why I ran.
In kind of a nutshell. You're just saying you don't like reductionism. You don't you don't like taking the mind and reducing it to the brain.
Even Yeah, I think reductionist. Reductionism is hugely important, and it's taught us so much. But I think it's mainly useful when the system is breaking down. You say, oh, they have sickle cell anemia. What's wrong? You know the blood systems I'm working, Well, the cells that compose that system are misshaped, or a person. I talk about the example of Charles Whitman in the sixties who shot a bunch of people from a bell tower in Texas and
it turned out he had a tumor in his brain. Well, he wasn't able to make a good free choice because his brain didn't support it. And so I would say that reductionism mainly works when you're trying to explain why the system has failed. But then if you're going to talk about what the system does, you know, then you need to know what's going on at the higher level. When I drive out to the interstate, I either go left or right. None of my machinery determines which way
it is. It's my intention to go to either Saint Louis or Kansas City. That's controlling my machinery in that case.
Yeah, I assume you've read the book Freedom Evolves by Daniel Dennett.
I have leafed through. Its pretty dense stuff, but a lot of good, good idea.
It seems very very compatible with your argument, very compatible with the argument, except you put up more of a psychological machinery around it. I mean, he just argues that we have a lot of these abilities, that abilities that we evolve that give us a free will worth wanting. And that's essentially what you're saying. But you are able to flesh that out in a lot of ways with neuroscience and with self determination theory. Your your groundbreaking research
and goals. Yeah, your work, Your work has really been very impactful in the field of positive psychology, field of psychology overall. It's it's certainly influenced my work as well, I should say, and the work you've done, the breath of it on goals and as well as well being, and particularly the link between goals and well being is kind of your niche, that's.
That's your thing.
Yeah, I know, I see you, I see you, I see you, I get you. And it's really made a substantial impact. So to be in the field of psychology to be able to link that to the free will debate,
it just was super fascinating to me to read. I will say one of the things that was super fastating for me to read as well was your discussion of the default mode network, because I've been studying the default mode network with my colleagues and linking it to creative thinking, and you don't make that direct link, but you have a chapter on the default mode network, and you do have a separate chapter on creativity, and so maybe we can make that link together right now more explicit.
Well, I'm actually working on a review chapter right now with a self determination theory neuroscientist named Google Lee, where we're making that connection. We're asking the question, how do
we decide what to do next? And we're outlining that question using control theory and the cybernetic perspective, but we're also looking at the brain processes and we're concluding that there's interplay between central executive network, salience network and the default mode network, or there's back and forth between the prefernal cortex and consciousness of question arises as arises say in a creator's mind when they're trying to solve a problem and we don't know the answer to that question,
but the fact that it was a conscious experience broadcasts it to the broader or lower mind and starts to work on it at a non conscious level. And the mode network processes are a big part of that. And then the salience network at one point sort of notices WHOA, some thought that's just sort of wandered across the default mode view screen. It says that's important, and then we say, whoa, And then we can make a choice and maybe realize that we need to completely change what we've been doing
in our life. So in that last chapter in the book, I make a connection between the process of changing your life adopting a whole new set of goals, and the creative process using that four stage model of WALLAS of preparation, preparation, incubation, illumination, elaboration. And so yes, I am kind of trying to link those two chapters right now in this review article that we're writing. It is pretty exciting because I think it's the original stuff that we're pulling together.
That's great. Let me know if I can help it all. You know, if you just won't even talk to me about the research we've conducted on the topic, it might be beneficial.
You know, I would love to send you a just if you wouldn't mind taking a quick read of this draft when we finish.
It, Yeah, because i'd love to.
It could have a lot of holes then your expertise would be great to check them.
I'd love to. I'd love to. Yeah, I'm so excited that you're working in that. You know, we have listeners and might not be familiar with anything we're really talking about right now, So let's talk a little about what the default mode network. What the world are we talking about.
There seems to be a particular netbrain network that cognitive neuroscientists discovered by accident because they didn't really seem to care much about what people were doing in the fMRI machine when they weren't doing the task that was assigned to them, and it seemed to be like, oh wow, maybe there's some value to the inner stream of consciousness,
as William James would put it. How would you characterize the major functions of the default midle network, because there's a lot of like kind of debate in the field about exactly what it does well.
It does a bunch of different things, that's true. I think it's involved both in executive control and in mind wandering, which makes it hard to disentangle all the different stuff. But I think of it as when we're just sort of not doing anything in particular. We don't have a cybernetic tope loop, we don't have a goal that's active in our mind. We're not doing something. We're just hanging out in our mind during sort of a free flowing state.
And so, you know, we used to think that didn't mean anything, it was just mind wandering, But no, we think default activity is critical for sort of processing what's going on and connecting things up with our goals and motives and linking memories in spontaneous ways that can arise to consciousness and sometimes can present us with the Aha moment that this is the solution to the question or
the problem I've been trying to solve. So the default mode network, I think, arguably is us, you know, when we're not doing anything, as compared to the focused mode when we're trying to solve a problem, but a lot of times we're not doing that. We're just kind of zoning along, but that doesn't mean we're not doing anything.
It's kind of like dreaming, but at a more conscious level, we're kind of processing, making connections, wondering stuff and remembering things and reflecting on what somebody said the other day and maybe feeling guilty because we haven't connected with our sick friend that we heard about, and the friend wonders about us and the bugs a little bit, and then we realized, Hey, I saw this great cake baking recipe, and I know I could bake that cake for my friend and take it to him or heart. So it's
the default mode. Network is the part between action, but it's critical because it provides a lot of the spark to return to the next action, to adopt the next goal, and we don't know a lot about that process, to be honest, it's surprising how little personality and cybernetic models have looked at that. Like even the Carver and Shire model of goals doesn't say where did the goals come from? How do we get that goal? It just said we picked the action. That's that's a determined by the higher
level goals in our system. Right, I want to be a compassionate person, so I will picking to do that you know, expresses my compassion. But you know, a lot of times we're doing something new, we're waning it and we don't have any big pre existing idea, but we're still figuring out what to do next. I think the default mode has a lot to do with that. But there's a lot to be figured out with that as well. And I'm just starting to learn about the neuroscience of all this.
Yeah, it's tricky stuff. One thing I do want to double click on is I do think a lot of the functions of the default mode network are to form the core of human existence. That's how I freezed it, and I do think that's true. I think that the default Moile network can couple and decouple with the executive attention network to various degrees depending on the different stages
of the creative process. Yeah, for different you know, sometimes we can focus intensely on our daydreams so we can have positive as my mentor Dromo Singer called positive constructive daydreaming. Is probably when the default mode is linked and coupled our deep attention resources or working memory resources. So yeah, these things could be all these different kind of brain networks. You also mentioned the salience network, which I think is one of the most underrated brain networks. I'm glad that
you mentioned the salience network. That seems to be really important for creativity to be able to see what may count as a creative solution in the first place. So I think that's wonderful that you brought that in. But all these kinds of brain networks couple and decouple constantly. You know that it's where it's fall and back and forth, you know, and and so you know, the brains are constantly dynamic.
You know.
You know all this, But I think we need to explain this to to our listeners. You know, But how
it all unpinges on the free will debate. It's still not completely clear to me because someone can say that, you know, all this is is maybe you're talking about human will, but it's not free will, because a lot of people narrowly view free will as could you have done differently in that specific if you rewinded the tape at that specific precise moment, would you ever have acted differently than and you're talking a lot about the things we do after the moment to change the course of
our future, you know, because I've called it the imagination network. I've called the default mode the imagination network because it can impact our future. But does it really impact the notion of free will?
Though? Yeah, well again I'm not arguing for magic free will independent of all the machioney. I think that we have this mental ability to take stock of who we are, where we are, and what we want and make some decisions, and could we have done differently? I think that almost might be a nonsensical question, because you, first of all, you can't go back to that moment and say, okay, do something different or not. It's already happened, and so
everything that's already happened has already happened. So I don't to ask could you have done differently? Is to ask could the universe have turned out any differently at this moment? Since it began four billion years ago? It's kind of the same question. I think it's more useful to ask
could I have done differently? And if you think about it, a lot of times you were poised between two or three almost equally attractive options, and you know, you picked one, and maybe you later realize you wished you hadn't done that, and so you would pick differently the next time. But at the time, you picked the thing that looked most appealing, And so why would you have picked differently from that? You picked the thing that you wanted? And so why would it be free will to think that you have
the capacity to pick what you don't want? And actually, now that I think about it, that's part of what I'm saying free will is we have the capacity to pick what we don't want. Yeah, for you won't Yeah, I mean we can make bad decisions. We can look. The last chapter of my book talks about a woman who made a bad, weird decision decades ago and it's been miserable ever since, until finally her misery. Misery inspired her to start asking the questions what do I really want?
Where her non conscious mind started to provide her with some alternatives until she was finally able to pick something different. And I think that's all you can really ask for, you know, an agent regarding free will, the ability to pick what we think we want and learn from our mistakes.
From mistakes, well, that that takes us out of the realm of how a lot of philosophers define narrowly they defined. It's like, it's like they can't think of free will outside of the rewind the tape thing. Do you know what I mean?
Yeah, I don't they're rewind the tape thing, doesn't It's a thought experiment that I don't think is very co here.
Can can drop on the call it right there.
I mean, I'm probably just not getting you.
Should have snapped, you should have snapped with that and get a little sassy, get a little sassy over there. Well you know, no, I hear you, brother, I hear you, brother. I'm a big fan of the a lot of Daniel Dennet's writings on the abilities that are they give us a free will worth One time, I think a lot of things I was not thinking, Yeah it's so okay, Well you'll see a great friend, a great friend there of ideas, you know, so I've always yeah, I'm I'm
a big I'm a big fan of those ideas. I'm a big fan of of you making the case that a lot of the kinds of system two functions we're talking about are things that they are free will is worth wanting in the Daniel Dennitts terms, but in your terms, you're saying there's You're straight up saying that's free will. And so that's fascinating because you you're just like straight up You're like no, You're like, no, we got more free will than you realize.
We're doomed to have free will. Yeah, that's a funny way to flat it around. But that's that's the existentialist in me. You know, that's saying, yeah, there ain't nobody else making our choices but us. We might like to think so, but we're responsible. And that's scary, but it's also tremendously empowering if you fully grasp it.
Hmm. Yeah, And I know that's another major theme of your work, is the link between freedom and responsibility. I assume you've read Roll May's stuff. Yeah, yeah, in the sixties.
I'm an old humanist going from way back, mostly a rogarian, but yeah, some of the other folks as well, I've read.
Yeah, roll May wrote beautifully about about that interplay, and I think I love that you brought in, brought that in, you know, to this this whole debate. And it's very interesting because you have like a whole chapter the problem of too much freedom, the chapter that's the chapter you have. So it's like, it's interesting because there's there's kind of
different continuums that one can make in this argument. One could say, a lot of people, a lot of philosophers of mine, say, especially determined to say, look, we have a heck of a lot less free will than we realize we have. Then there are sums like, actually, we have more than we realize. But then I think you're even to the right of that continuum and saying we have so much free will that we don't know what to do with it. In a way, do you think do you and this might be controversial, but do you
think like it's easier being a determinist? Like if you're a hard determinist, do you feel like you're evading your responsibility, your destiny?
You know, I think that hard determinism is seductive.
It's a deep question.
It's seductive because it seems like the most scientifically rigorous position to take, and it's the position that goes along with the scientific ideal of putting our subjective wants and values aside and being guided by the facts. Right, And so we have this wishful thinking of wanting free will, but as true scientists, we have to put that aside.
I disagree with that. I think when we do that, it's bad for us because we're accepting an idea that isn't true and we're going to negatively impact our own functioning. Quite a bit of research, experimental research on what happens when you convince people that determinism is true, and they become less moral, less able to self regulate, less pro social, number they become numb to pain. So if you convince people yeah, I'm serious the code, I.
Want to ask you a follow up question to that, because is has anyone ever done the study on different philosophers and psychologists and what they believe in their actual morality? Like that? From that level, wouldn't that be interesting? Wouldn't that be an interesting study like are hard determinists more immoral? You know?
I would be a fascinating study. And a version that I've thought about it is does an evolutionary psychologist who thinks that men evolve to be philanderers have less ability to control their right unfortunate choices with their female graduate students? You know, I think free will can determinism? Can you know, make you think you're not responsible. I had to do that. Yeah, so that's another you're right besides the well being hit
that you take with those beliefs. Yeah, I think it's a dangerous belief.
Wow, you even go so far to say that that that it's a dangerous belief.
You know, I don't care. I'm getting to the end of my career. I'll just say what I think.
And you have no fucks to give about for you, about for you, Ken, Ken's like I got zeros to give in the in this debate, it's you. No, I hear you. The idea, whether or not it's a dangerous idea is is? I can again, I can hear the voice in my head of the hard determinists saying, because I've debated so much of them, so I can kind of like hear what their counter to everything you say is.
And I think they would say that it makes them more compassionate because you realize that people, even in their most poor choices, really didn't have a choice ultimately, ultimately, and that that should give us all more more compassion for each other, not less. I can hear them saying that as a rebuttal to what you're saying.
Yeah, and that's kind of what my dad was saying. It's a bit of a liberal perspective of you, you know, forgive people of their crimes if they came from a terrible, you know background. And I don't think I don't think we can really afford to say that because the question of who is really off the hook versus isn't it's very tricky. I think you're only really off the hook if you've got some organic problems. And that's once again, determinism only makes sense when there's a problem down in
the machinery, or reductionism only makes sense. So if your machinery is off, then okay, you're off the hook. But if you're just making bad choices and then you're saying, well, I couldn't help it, I think that's again a dangerous thing to a dangerous road to go down. Wow.
Okay, okay, let's end this interview talking a little about the importance of brains working together. You know you this chapter called a Living Will Together Man, have you with the extended brain hypothesis that uh, David Chalmers and Andy Clark put forward and that Annie Murphy Paul wrote about in a recent book.
Nope and that sounds like another one. I got to check it out. I think I'm going to be familiar with the arguments once you explain it to me quickly.
Oh yeah, you'll, you'll definitely. I mean, well, just that there are there are brains, don't stop and start enclosed in this head, That we are deeply, deeply embodied and connected to others, and our brain is extended beyond just this skin here.
It's just it.
Seems very much in line with your your Living Well Together chapter, we talk about how we really influence each other's We really influence each other's free will in profound ways. Right, it's not all strictly in an individual pursuit the pursuit of free will, all right.
Yeah, And that sounds consistent with what I've been what I say in the book about this multi level hierarchy of organization where we are also nested within groups of other minds and we're influenced by them, but we also influence them, and it's critical for our well being and our adaptation, I would argue, to be able to form coherent groups, alliances, coalitions, and evolutionary terminology, and so we're not just not just these abstract entities stuck in our heads.
We're also connected to other minds out there in the world, hopefully in a way that benefits everybody. So it sounds like a really cool idea. In another book, I have to go look up, Scott.
Yeah, yeah, look it up.
Let me just look up real quick.
The title of Manny Murphy Paul's new book, she basically summarizes the work Urr. Book is called The Extended Mind by Annie Murphy Paul. The subtitle is The Power of Thinking Outside the Brain. Annie's a dear friend of mine. And yeah, I think it's.
A cool book.
Yeah, and I think I do like that He of us thinking about free will more than just an individualistic pursuit, right, I mean, we influence each other's and each other in such profound ways. We limit each other's freedom, not just internally but also externally. The liberals got something right there to a certain degree. Your father is right, but it's not the whole story, but you know it is part of the story for sure.
Yeah.
Yeah, well, this is this has been great. Is there anything else you want to add that you haven't said?
I guess I would just reiterate that I can't prove and nobody can prove that free will exists. I think it's likely if you think about it the right way, and I think about it the way Kristen lifts list
laid out is philosophical arguments. But even if it's not true, the illusion of freedom, if you want to call that, makes a huge difference, and it might operate like a kind of placebo effect that it even though it's an illusion, it makes itself true to a considerable extent in that if you believe in it, suddenly you're doing things that are better for you and making you happier and making
you adapt and thrive to a greater extent. So whether you want to call that an illusion, I think is you know, I think it's going too far to just say it's an illusion. I'd say it's an adaptation. But you know, it can go around and around with these things linguistics.
You can call it an adaptive illusion, but then you don't really like calling it an illusion. Yeah, no, I hear you. I mean it's like religion, right, like or.
Belief in God.
Yeah, you know, like we don't know for sure. It's sort of like a similar argument to what you're saying. I mean, we probably won't never know while we're alive. You know, maybe we'll find out someday. Oh hey, God, you do exist after all. But it's hard. It's hard to know that right now.
Yeah, right, And I don't know. I don't know the truth of this, and neither does anybody else. But it's true that it is like a religion to people. You know, determinism is like a religion to people. Free will might be like a religion to me. I don't know. I would agree with Sam Harris. I do think that God is a delusion, that religion is a delusion. But I can't be sure about that either. So really you just have to be sort of agnostic if you're going to be humble in the.
End, Ken Sheldon letting it all hang out here at the end of his career. God is good. But we have free will. That's that's interesting. Usually you find a lot of the really deep religious Christians believe we have free will. It's an interesting isn't that interesting? You often find they do believe in free will.
God gave it to you.
Well, that's what it is. I guess is that God gave it to us to us, But there you go, Well, who gave us evolution?
This is a chance prodcast.
Anyway. I won't go down that rabbit hole too much at this point, but we can do that over some beers someday or some wine. Really great chatting with you, and thanks for reading this really provocative book.
I appreciate it. It was fun reconnecting with you, and we should do it more often.
Likewise, thanks for listening to this episode of The Psychology Podcast. If you'd like to react in some way to something you heard, I encourage you to join in the discussion at thus psychology podcast dot com. We're on our YouTube page, The Psychology Podcast. We also put up some videos of some episodes on our YouTube page as well, so you'll want to check that out. Thanks for being such a great supporter of the show, and tune in next time for more on the mind, brain, behavior, and creativity.